EconGraphs Logo BETA
Note: These explanations are in the process of being adapted from my textbook.
I'm trying to make them each a "standalone" treatment of a concept, but there may still
be references to the narrative flow of the book that I have yet to remove.
This work is under development and has not yet been professionally edited.
If you catch a typo or error, or just have a suggestion, please submit a note here. Thanks!

Preferences over Present vs. Future Consumption


The standard analysis of consumer preferences involves comparing several “goods” – for example, apples and bananas. However, the same framework can be adjust to allow for the goods in question to be consumption in different time periods. For example, “good 1” can be the amount of money you currently have (or the quantity of goods you currently consume), and “good 2” can be the amount of money or goods you have in the future.

Technically, one could have any preferences over consumption in different time periods, just as one could have any preferences over any goods. However one models these preferences, though, there’s a fundamental breakdown between how one feels about consumption within a time period, and how one thinks about comparing consumption across time periods.

One elegant (but almost certainly flawed) way of thinking about these preferences is to assume that the way you feel about money within a time period is independent of the time period: that is, consuming €100 today gives you exactly as much utility today as consuming $€100$ tomorrow would give you tomorrow. In other words, there is some “indirect utility” function $v(c)$ which relates monetary consumption $c$ (in dollars) with happiness (in utils) within a given time period.

However, your present self doesn’t value current consumption and future consumption equally: if you’re impatient, or present-biased, you might value current your utility over your own future utility. Thus, your overall utility, as viewed from the present, might have a form something like \(u(c_1,c_2) = v(c_1) + \beta v(c_2)\) where $\beta < 1$ represents the amount by which you “discount” future utility.

In fact, we’ve already seen a number of utility functions which have this general form. In particular, if $v(c) = \ln c$, then intertemporal preferences may be represented by the Cobb-Douglas utility function \(u(c_1,c_2) = \ln c_1 + \beta \ln c_2\) The MRS of this function would be \(MRS = {c_2 \over \beta c_1}\) The following graph illustrates some indifference curves for this utility function. Try playing around with the $\beta$ parameter and the consumption bundle, and see how the MRS changes.

As a first approximation of modeling preferences over time, this has a lot going for it:

While this works for the metaphor of two periods, for a long time economists took this a step further, postulating that people would discount a future stream of payments exponentially: \(u(c_1,c_2,...,c_T) = v(c_1) + \beta v(c_2) + \beta^2 v(c_3) + \cdots \beta^{T-1}v(c_T)\) This goes beyond saying that you’re just present-biased: it hypothesizes that “rational” people have time-consistent preferences. That is, it says the way you compare consumption today and consumption tomorrow is exactly the same way as you compare consumption, say, 1000 days from now with consumption 1001 days from now. A large literature in behavioral economics has pretty well disproved this hypothesis, and in its placed offered a range of other ways to think about how people make intertemporal choices.

But as with all our utility functions, realism is not our goal: we’re trying to model the kind of tensions that exist in evaluating how someone might think about distributing their consumption across time, and for those purposes the metaphor of a two-period model with a “patience” parameter $\beta$ works just fine.

Next: The Intertemporal Budget Constraint
Copyright (c) Christopher Makler / econgraphs.org